/Virtue theory and abortion pdf

Virtue theory and abortion pdf

Please forward this error virtue theory and abortion pdf to 198. David Johnson: What Does Academic Skepticism Presuppose?

Jordan Bartol: Is Intercultural Critique Possible? New Classical Natural Law theory, is the name given a particular revival and revision of Thomistic Natural Law theory, initiated in the 1960s by Germain Grisez. Grisez’s initial collaborators included Joseph Boyle, John Finnis and Olaf Tollefsen. May, Christian Brugger, and Christopher Tollefsen have done work on the NNL.

Articulation and defense of the theory began with the publication of Grisez’s interpretative essay on St. Thomas’s first principle of practical reason, in 1965. Although that essay established some of the controversial theses of the new view, in particular, that the foundation of practical reason is in a foundational practical recognition of certain basic goods, and that no inference from theoretical truths concerning human nature is necessary or possible, Grisez was there attempting to provide an accurate interpretation of St. Subsequent work, while deeply indebted to St. The ultimate end of human beings.

In his early works, Grisez articulated a number of theses that have been developed by the New Natural Lawyers in the subsequent four decades. Further foundational considerations were defended by Grisez, Finnis, and Boyle in several books and articles, and in essays written individually by the three thinkers. First, the New Natural Law view holds that practical reason, that is, is reason oriented towards action, grasps as self-evidently desirable a number of basic goods. God, and harmony among a person’s judgments, choices, feelings, and behavior. As grasped by practical reason, the basic goods give foundational reasons for action to human agents. Second, these goods, and most of their instantiations in action, are held to be incommensurable with one another. That is to say, there is no natural hierarchy of goodness such that one good may be said to offer all the good of another plus more.

The same is generally true of particular instantiations of the goods: one way of working, playing, or pursuing knowledge, for example, may offer benefits that are not weighable by a common standard of goodness in relation to instantiations of the other goods, or even instantiations of the same good. This point about incommensurability has emerged as central to the defense of the possibility of free choice, especially in recent work by Boyle. Third, and in consequence of the first two points, the judgments of practical reason in recognizing the basic goods and directing agents to pursuit of those goods are not yet moral. Rather, practical reason’s apprehension of and directedness to the goods is a condition for human actions, all of which, to be genuine actions, must be oriented to some good. Morality enters in only at the level of deliberation and choice as regards which goods, or which instantiations of goods, to pursue when faced with desirable options for choice. The New Natural Lawyers have offered various formulations of a first principle of morality, which captures a reasonable openness to all the goods across all persons. The differences between these will be discussed in the section on the ultimate end.

All three claims have been disputed. Against the second, many have objected that there is a hierarchy of goods, with theoretical knowledge, or knowledge of or friendship with God at the top. Those who object on either of these two grounds object thereby to the first principle of morality, as do proportionalists, who deny that it is always wrong intentionally to act against basic goods. Others object to the claim that the first principle of practical reason is other than the first principle of morality. Finally, among the New Natural Lawyers there is some disagreement as to whether or not practical reasonableness, understood as moral virtue, should be understood as a basic good.

The casuistry of the New Natural Law theory is in large part a function of a working out of the implications of the first principle of morality, a principle that requires openness to, pursuit of, and no intentional damage to, the basic goods across all persons. These modes direct agents to certain kinds of acts, and away from others, by taking into account the ways in which emotions and non-morally integrated feelings could distort an agent’s openness to the goods, and to other persons’ fulfillment in the goods. Thus, through hostility towards a good, on the one hand, or enthusiasm for some good, on the other, agents might be tempted to damage or destroy an instance of the goods. Or, through arbitrary preference of self, or those close to one, an agent might unfairly allow damages to be inflicted on another while pursuing a good himself. These modes of responsibility can in turn be further specified with respect to particular kinds of actions. The best known work of the New Natural Lawyers has focused on the specification of two of the modes mentioned above, both of which forbid intentional damage or destruction of a basic good, whether because of hostility, or because of enthusiasm for some good.